What Is Descartes’ Conclusion? A Comprehensive Overview

What is the conclusion that Descartes reached after his famous method of doubt? This question has been debated by philosophers for centuries. Descartes sought to find a set of beliefs that could not be rationally disputed, but did he succeed? His method of doubt, which aimed to wipe the epistemic slate clean and start afresh, forms the basis of modern analytic philosophy. However, his standard for knowledge – that certainty is necessary – has been challenged by contemporary theorists. In this blog post, we will explore Descartes’ conclusion and its implications for our understanding of knowledge.

What Is Descartes Conclusion

Introduction To Descartes’ Method Of Doubt

The method of doubt, also known as Cartesian doubt or methodical doubt, is a central element in René Descartes’ philosophy. It is a way of seeking certainty by systematically doubting everything. Descartes developed this method after confronting the many discussions held by traditional scholastics that seemed to yield no results. He saw the cause in the fact that no undoubted certainties had yet been found in philosophy on which to build. Therefore, he proposed to doubt everything that could possibly be doubted, even the scientific insights of the time and the Holy Scriptures. If you leave out everything that can be doubted, you are left with only that which is necessarily true, according to Descartes. This process eventually led Descartes to an absolute knowledge, the cogito. Among other things, it enabled him to demonstrate, empirically rather than logically, the existence of human freedom.

The Search For Indubitable Beliefs

Descartes’ philosophical project was to find a foundation for obtaining certain knowledge, which was brought about by the emerging natural sciences. He believed that the best way to begin a search for indubitable knowledge was by subjecting all his beliefs to a radical skeptical attack, even if this doubt would be considered ridiculous in ordinary life. Descartes went down the path of methodical doubt because he realized that it was necessary “to demolish everything completely and start again right from the foundations”.

In order for Descartes to lay the skeptical hypotheses to rest and find a foundation for certain knowledge, he needed to slay the Malicious Demon. Descartes’ philosophical project was not just about doubting everything but also finding a way to establish indubitable beliefs. Once he discovered Cogito, Descartes argued that it could serve as a foundation for how to find other truths that were certain. He proposed that Cogito was undeniably true because it was clear and distinct. These qualities became the standard against which all other beliefs could be evaluated.

Descartes argued that clarity and distinctness rule, derived from Cogito, could justify our beliefs about the external world. But what verified the clarity-and-distinctness rule? God’s existence, Descartes argued. By reflecting on his idea of God, he argued that God exists. Descartes then argued that a truthful, good God would not allow us to be deceived when we understand objects clearly and distinctly, and so God would not allow us to routinely have false beliefs.

Descartes’ Standard For Knowledge: Certainty

Descartes’ standard for knowledge is based on the idea that a belief can only be considered knowledge if it meets a certain level of certainty. He believed that in order for a belief to be known, it must be certain and cannot be false. This standard was set by Descartes in response to his skepticism towards knowledge gained through the senses. He argued that our senses cannot meet this standard, and therefore, we cannot know anything on the basis of our senses alone.

However, many contemporary theorists of knowledge tend to deny that knowledge requires certainty. They argue that we can know some claim, yet not be certain that it is true. This is known as “fallibilism.” Descartes’ standard for knowledge is problematic because almost no beliefs meet it. He thought he could show how our ordinary knowledge claims are ultimately based on the Cogito, but most philosophers have not been convinced by his case.

The epistemic lesson of the Cogito is that if certainty is a necessary requirement for knowledge, we are left with very little knowledge indeed. The challenge, however, is that if certainty is not required for knowledge, what is? Descartes firmly believed that reason is a native gift of humans and that true knowledge can be directly gleaned not from books but only through the methodical application of reason. He believed that if he presented all his arguments as logical trains of thought, then anyone could understand them and nobody could help but be swayed.

Implications For Modern Epistemology

Descartes’ philosophical inquiry into knowledge and science has significant implications for modern epistemology. One of the key takeaways from his work is the idea that certainty is necessary for knowledge. Descartes believed that we can only claim to know something if we are absolutely certain of it. However, many contemporary theorists of knowledge argue that certainty is not a requirement for knowledge. They contend that we can have knowledge of something without being completely certain of its truth.

This debate over the role of certainty in knowledge has important implications for modern epistemology. If certainty is necessary for knowledge, then our knowledge claims are severely limited. We may only be able to claim knowledge of a very small number of things, as very few beliefs meet the standard of absolute certainty. On the other hand, if certainty is not required for knowledge, then we have a much broader range of knowledge claims available to us.

Descartes’ method of doubt also has implications for modern epistemology. His strategy of considering false any belief that falls prey to doubt can be seen as a precursor to contemporary skepticism. Many modern philosophers have adopted a similar approach, arguing that we should be skeptical of our beliefs until they can be adequately justified.

Conclusion: Descartes’ Legacy In Philosophy

Descartes is widely regarded as one of the most influential philosophers in history. His contributions to mathematics, natural philosophy, and metaphysics have had a lasting impact on modern thought. Descartes’ most famous philosophical contribution is his method of doubt, which he developed in order to arrive at certain knowledge. This method involves doubting everything that can be doubted until only what is indubitable remains.

Descartes’ legacy in philosophy is multifaceted. He is remembered for his mechanistic view of the natural world, which held that all physical phenomena can be explained in terms of matter and motion. This perspective paved the way for the scientific revolution and the development of modern physics. Additionally, Descartes’ mind-body dualism has been a topic of debate for centuries. His view that the mind and body are separate entities has influenced modern psychology and neuroscience.

Descartes’ arguments for the existence of God have also had a lasting impact on philosophy. His ontological argument, which attempts to prove the existence of God through reason alone, has been the subject of much debate and criticism. However, it remains an important contribution to the philosophy of religion.

Overall, Descartes’ legacy in philosophy is marked by his contributions to mathematics, natural philosophy, metaphysics, and the philosophy of religion. His ideas have influenced countless thinkers and continue to shape modern thought.

About The Author